Lefebvre V.A., Webber J.A. Functions of Fast Reflexion in Bipolar Choice //Reflexive processes and control. Vol.1, N1. P.29-40.

*****

FUNCTIONS OF FAST REFLEXION IN BIPOLAR CHOICE

Vladimir A. Lefebvre (USA), Jack Adams-Webber (Canada)

Vladimir A. Lefebvre

University of California,

Irvine, USA, professor

Jack Adams-Webber

Brock University, Ontario,

Canada, professor

Introduction

Our view of “reflexion” has been essentially broadened during the last twenty years. Traditionally we have considered it to consist of the conscious constructing of images of the self and others by human beings. Now we have evidence that there is a reflexion of another nature as well. It is as if an

inborn informational processor is built in into human psyche whose function is to automatically create these images together with their subjective domains. This processor generates a specific specter of human responses not controlled consciously and running extremely fast (one-two milliseconds). This type of reflexion, as distinct from the traditional concept is called fast reflexion (Lefebvre, 1987). In this paper we will decipher the mathematical laws governing the automatic functioning of this inborn processor and show how they reveal themselves in human behavior (Adams-Webber, 1996a). The result of this analysis will be a formal model of the subject with fast reflexion.

Ideally, global theoretical models ought to possess two properties: integrity and uniformity. Integrity means that the model must be able to reflect simultaneously the subjectís perception, behavior, and inner domain. Uniformity requires that different aspects of the subjectís activity must be described in terms of the same theoretical language. The general method for attaining these two properties is to represent the subject as a composition of mathematical functions. Various elements of this composition are interpreted

as “inputs” and “outputs” and as images of the self and of other subjects. These images can have their own inner domain containing images of the next order. As a result, we succeed in producing a unified functional description of the subject’s inner and external activity. A composition of mathematical functions is also a function. It describes the subject’s behavior. Therefore, the composition’s structure reflects not only the subject’s inner domain, but also the macrostructure of a computational process generating behavior. In the simplest cases, when the “global” function of behavior is known in advance, information about the mental domain can be obtained from a purely mathematical analysis of the properties of the function.

Introduction of the concept of reflexion into psychology

It is no accident that early steps in this direction were taken in Russia, where the dominance of behaviorism has been historically less oppressive than in America. These preliminary steps were related to a discovery of a sudden interruption of subjects’ automatized processes in experimental games. Typical laboratory experiments included two phases. In the first phase, a computer program playing the role of an opponent “taught” subjects a particular mode of behavior which was advantageous for them. Then, in the

second phase, the program suddenly changed its tactics in such a way that the same mode of behavior became disadvantageous. In these experiments, it was discovered that the subjects would alter their behavior abruptly. No evidence of gradual retraining was observed (Lefebvre, 1967; 1969; 1972; 1977a; Baranov & Trudoliubov, 1969a,b; Lepsky, 1969).

The abrupt change from a previous automatized activity was often accompanied by some “insight” or “realization”: the subjects suddenly “understood” that their opponent had, during the first phase of the experiment, deliberately misled them. Under this operational interpretation, the concept of “realization” acquired a functional meaning. It was believed to be connected, if not with the reorganization of human automatized activity, then at least with its instant blocking. Nonetheless, the use of terms such as “realization”, “understanding”, “intention”, whose meanings depend significantly on the context, threatened a return to pre-behaviorist “mentalism” and abandonment of the commitment to the scientific falsification of hypotheses.

An alternative approach was to construct simple formal models of subjects in the framework of which concepts reflecting the human subjective domain could acquire clear and unambiguous meaning. This approach led to the construction of several particular models of the subject with reflexion. In this paper we shall limit our consideration to one line of the development of such models associated with studying the bipolar choice (Lefebvre, 1977b; 1980; 1982; 1992; V.A.Lefebvre, V.D.Lefebvre, Adams-Webber, 1986; Krylov, 1994; Miller & Sulcoski, 1999). This theoretical model gave rise to many new methodological problems which have been addressed in an extensive literature (Adams-Webber, 1987; 1995; Batchelder, 1987; Kauffman, 1990; Lefebvre, 1987; 1995; Levitin, 1987; Popper, 1992; Rapoport, 1990; Schreider, 1994; 1998; Townsend, 1983; 1990; Wheeler, 1987; Zajonc, 1987).

Mechanism for generating images of the self and others

The hypothesis of existence of the inner processor for generating fast reflexion can be described as follows (Lefebvre, 1985):

(1) A person possesses an inner formal mechanism for modeling the self and others. This mechanism is universal and does not depend on the particular culture to which a person belongs.

(2) The models of the self and other are reflexive; that is, these models may themselves contain models of the self and other, and so on.

(3) The inner formal mechanism for modeling includes a computational process, which is automatic and does not depend on conscious will. This process predetermines a person’s responses in a situation of choice between “good” and “bad”, and it also generates his inner feelings, such as

guilt and condemnation.

(4) The models of the self and of the other also have this computational

ability, which allows a person to model automatically his own and his

partner’s inner feelings, providing information that is unavailable to direct

observation.

Let us mention further that this human modeling mechanism is not a chain of verbal reasoning such as “I think that he thinks that I think,” etc. Such chains are purely linguistic structures. In contrast, we are concerned with the direct computational modeling of the self and other which proceeds automatically and independently of inner speech (Lefebvre, 1985, pp. 291-292).

This hypothesis was published sixteen years ago as more than a methodological declaration. It contained a detailed description of a possible mechanism for cognitive computations; however, experimental evidence in its favor began to appear only recently. For example, Hughes and Cutting (1999) demonstrated that children’s ability to reproduce other persons’ inner domains operates automatically and does not depend on verbal development.

The mechanism for the automated generation of images of the self and others described in this section lies outside the framework of the traditional understanding of reflexion as a human conscious constructive activity connected with his will and desire. While constructing one’s own image consciously a person may provide it with many features of his own choice. Unlike this ‘creative’ activity, the processor under consideration is inseparable from the human being itself. The subject in a normal state does not sense its presence. One cannot eliminate the control of this processor by an effort of will, which is similar to the impossibility of intentionally ceasing to understand words in one’s own native language. We have called the automatic process of generating the images fast reflexion, in order to avoid confusion with a conscious process of comprehending the self and others.

Reflexive model of bipolar choice

The model represents a subject facing the choice between two alternatives, A and B. One of them, A, plays the role of the positive pole, and the other that of the negative pole (Lefebvre, 1977b; 1980; 1995; 1997). In the simplest case, when the subject’s inner world does not contain the images of other subjects, his choice can be described by the function X1 = f (x1,x2,x3), where all variables take their values from the interval [0,1] (see Appendix). The value of x3 is the subject’s intention to choose the positive pole. The greater x3, the more the “desire” to make this choice. The value of X1 is interpreted as the probability with which the subject is ready to choose the positive pole, A, in reality. The value of x1 is the world’s pressure toward the positive alternative A at the precise moment of choice. The value of x2 is the world’s pressure toward A which is expected by the subject based on prior experience. We can consider the values of x1 and (1 - x1) as normalized utility-measures of the alternatives A and B at the moment of choice, and the values of x2 and (1 - x2) as normalized expected utility-measures.

A mathematical analysis of the function X1 = f (x1,x2,x3) of three variables demonstrates that it can be represented as a composition of one particular function of two variables, F(x,y), and that such a representation is unique; that is, X1 = F (x1, F (x2,x3)). Function X2 = F (x2,x3) is interpreted as the image of the self possessed by the subject. Under this interpretation the subject has a functionally correct image of the self, since the same function, F (x,y), describes him from both his own perspective and external points of view. The first variable in this function, x, represents perceptual input, and the second variable, y, is a mental image of the self. Therefore, in considering the function F (x2,x3), which plays the role of an image of the self, we have to interpret the variable x2 as an image of the input, and the variable x3 as the subject’s mental representation of his image’s image of the self. To avoid confusion, we call this secondary image a model of the self. The variable x3 now takes on an additional meaning: it represents not only the subject’s intention, but also his model of the self. As a result we obtain a formal analogue of the macro-structure of the subject’s inner domain. This analogue is a structure of composition F (x1,F (x2,x3)). At the

same time, this structure describes the process involved in the cognitive computation of X1 : first, X2 = F (x2,x3) is computed, and then X1 = F (x1,X2).

The subject’s intention may depend on factors distinct from x1 and x2, and, in principle, can take on any value from [0,1]. In cases in which the intention depends only on x1 and x2, we assume that the subject’s cognitive mechanism coordinates both the subjective intention, x3, and an objective readiness, X1, in such a way that X1 = x3 (Lefebvre, 1992). This equation corresponds

to the statement that the subject has a correct model of the self.

Functional role of the image of the self

Theoretical models may assist in conducting thought experiments. With the help of such an experiment we will clarify the role which the subject’s image of the self plays in his activity. Let the subject face a moral choice. In his value system, alternative A is a good act, and alternative B a bad one. Suppose that on the basis of the previous experience the subject sees the world as pressing him toward choosing the positive pole, that is, x2 = 1. Let the subject have the intention of choosing the positive pole, that is, x3 = 1. With these data we find the value of the image of the self: X2 = F (1,1) = 1 (see Appendix). Thus, the subject “sees” himself performing a good deed. Suppose that at the moment of choice, the world exerts pressure on the subject to choose the negative pole, which means x1 = 0. Then the subject’s real choice will correspond to the value of the function X1 = F (0,F(1,1)) = 0, i.e., in reality the subject carries out a bad action. The next time a similar situation arises, the subject will expect the world to press him toward the negative pole, which means that the value of x2 is changed from 1 to 0. If the subject’s intention is still positive (x3 = 1), the value of his image of the self becomes X2 = F (0,1) = 0, and if the world keeps pressing toward a bad action (x1 = 0), his real choice will correspond to the value X1 = F (0,F(0,1)) = 1, that is, the subject will choose the positive pole. In the first case, the subject sees himself as “good” but commits a bad action (X1 = 0); in the second case, the subject sees himself as “bad” but performs a good action (X1 = 1). The image of the self plays the role the subject’s “conscience”: seeing oneself as “bad” prevents one from choosing the negative pole. It follows from the formal model that when the value of X2= 0, then the value of X1 º 1. Therefore, a possible function of the image of the self is to block some of the subject’s actions. If at x1 = 0 the value of an image of the self suddenly changes from X2 = 1 to X2 = 0, we can describe this change in standard introspective language as follows: “the world presses the subject

toward evil, but the subject imagines himself as being ready to commit a bad act, then feels a prick of conscience and refuses to obey the pressure of the world.”

The difference between automatized and deliberate choice

A distinction between automated and deliberate choice is traditionally based on the notion that a person sometimes consciously plans and then performs an actions as planned, while other times the phase of conscious planning is absent (Bargh & Chartrand, 1999). The reflexive model allows us to make a clear distinction between these two cases: the variable x3 represents the subject’s will (intention, desire); and the variable X1 represents his behavior. Only behavior which does not depend on a subject’s will can be called “automatic”; that is, the value of X1 does not depend on the value of x3. Similarly, a subject’s behavior can be called “deliberate” only if the identity X1 º x3 holds, i.e., it is entirely determined by his will. Finally, mixed cases are possible in which intention x3 influences X1, but does not entirely determine it.

Automatic choice

An automatic choice is possible only in such pairs x1 = a and x2 = b for which the value of the function X1 = f (a,b,x3) does not depend on the value of x3 (see Appendix). As an illustration we will consider an experiment described in Wegner and Wheatley (1999). Their subjects were asked to attempt to read the unconscious muscle movement of a participant confederate whose fingers were placed on top of their own on “yes” and “no” response keys. Then a subject heard a trivial question of the type, “Is the capital of the USA Washington, D.C.?”. In reality, the confederate did not hear the questions and so his finger movements could not depend on their content. Nevertheless, the subjects pushed the correct button 87% of the times. In 63% of the cases they thought that they were acting according to their own will, and in 37% they believed that they felt a slight movement of the confederate’s fingers.

In commenting on this experiment the authors write: “They answered correctly, in other words, but did not have a strong sense of willfully having done so and instead thought the confederate had played a significant part. The pattern of findings across six experiments suggests that the correct answers are produced automatically” (Wegner & Wheatley, 1999, p. 457).

This conclusion corresponds to the mechanism which is represented in the formal model. Certainly, the majority of the subjects did not have any doubts that Washington, D.C. is the capital of the USA. The pressure of the external world was a social ‘demand characteristic’ directed toward the positive pole “tell the truth,” in the given case, “yes,” so x1 = 1. After the first question the subjects expected the other questions to be of the same type: they anticipated pressure toward true answers; that is, x2 = 1. As shown

in the Appendix, under such conditions choice is automatic, that is, it does not depend on intention x3.

Deliberate choice

In this case the intention, x3, predetermines entirely the subject’s readiness, X1. In accordance with the model, this is possible only if both x1 = 0 and x2 = 0 simultaneously, that is, in the situation in which the world presses the subject to choose the negative pole (x1 = 0) and the subject’s expectation is the same (x2 = 0). Under this condition, X1 º x3, that is, any subject’s intention turns into his readiness, X1. At first glance it seems that such a representation of deliberate or “free” choice is bound up with a particular problem, since real people even when they know the correct answers, may exhibit willfulness and answer incorrectly. To clarify this situation we return to Wegner and Weatney’s experiment (1999), in which the subjects heard questions of the type, “Is the capital of the USA Washington, D.C.?” As we demonstrated earlier, the correct answers to these questions are automatic. But many social psychologists who conduct surveys encounter subjects’ “rebellion,” especially during a series of monotonious trivial questions. Doesn’t this fact contradict the model’s predictions? In fact, the formal model explains the psychological mechanism underlying such rebellion. As we already have demonstrated, in experiments of the Wegner-Weatney type the subject takes on values x1 = 1 and x2 = 1. Suppose that after he answers a number of trivial questions, his “value system” suddenly changes: the positive pole, the choice of “tell the truth”, becomes negative and the negative pole, the choice of “lie”, becomes positive. The social imperative “tell the truth” did not disappear, but now it is directed toward the negative pole. A pressure toward the new positive pole is equal to zero. So, x1 = 0 and x2 = 0, and the subject’s choice becomes deliberate. Thus, the

inversion of the poles stops the automatic mode of activity.

The golden section and other constant

An important impetus for the development of this model in the United States was a series of experiments based on bipolar dimensions of judgment represented by pairs of antonymous adjectives (such as strong-weak), within the framework of Kelly’s (1955) personal construct theory, summarized by Adams-Webber (1996b). In the early 1970s an unexpected finding was obtained repeatedly (Adams-Webber & Benjafield, 1973; Benjafield & Adams-Webber, 1976): experimental subjects, on average, assigned their personal acquaintances to the positive poles of dimensions with a relative frequency of 0.62. Benjafield and Adams-Webber (1976) conjectured that the theoretical value of this constant might be the golden section ((Ö5-1)/2=0.618...).

The first attempt to explain the underlying psychological mechanism and specify the conditions for the appearance of the golden section in such experiments was formulated with the help of the reflexive model (Lefebvre, 1985). In accordance with this model, the golden section appears under two conditions:

(1) The subject does not have an operational criterion for determining whether a given object actially possesses the quality the presence of absence of which he must judge.

(2) The act of ascribing this quality to the object plays the role of the positive pole and the act of rejecting it that of the negative pole.

Let us clarify condition (2). It is not important that a given quality is positive or negative in its essence; the important factor is the subject’s evaluation of ascribing this quality to the object. For example, suppose someone bought a defective watch; in evaluating this purchase in terms of the construct ‘failure-success’ we have to consider ‘failure’ to be the positive pole and ‘success’ to be the negative pole. To test the model’s predictions, we need to analyze data from experiments in which both conditions specified above were satisfied. Several experiments conducted within the framework of the investigation of “mere exposure” (Zajonc, 1968) meet the criterion, especially those requiring subjects to choose between two patterns, one of which had been previously presented with an extremely short exposure time of 1-3 milliseconds (Kunst-Wilson & Zajonc, 1980). As shown in previous experiments, this time is inadequate for the subjects to memorize a pattern consciously, however, the “old” alternative, that is the one shown previously, was chosen by the subjects more often (Kunst-Wilson & Zajonc, 1980). We might reason that the prior exposure of patterns orients the pairs shown in the second phase of these experiments. Each “old” pattern assumes the role of the positive alternative, and its “new” counterpart that of the negative alternative. If we take this assumption into consideration, then in accordance with the reflexive model, the “old” alternative must be chosen not just “more often”, but with the relative frequency of 0.62. We analyzed all of the available data from similar experiments (Lefebvre, 1995) and obtained the following results:

Kunst-Wilson & Zajonc (1980), 0.60;

Seamon, Brody & Kanff (1983), 0.61;

Mandler, Nakamura & Van Zandt (1987), 0.62;

Bonano & Stillings (1986), 0.66, 0.63, 0.62, 0.61, 0.63, 0.62.

The last line contains six results because the authors conducted six independent experiments. We see that the data cluster around the value 0.62, which is exactly what the reflexive model predicts.

The reflexive model yields numerical predictions also for cases in which, prior to the beginning of an experiment, the subjects develop the intention to evaluate objects only positively or only negatively. In the first case, x3 = 1, and the model predicts that the subjects will make positive evaluations with the probability X1 = (2/3); in the second case, x3 = 0, the model predicts that the probability of positive evaluations be X1 = (1/2).

Special experiments with bipolar constructs in which the subjects’ intentions were determined, have shown that with positive intentions the frequency of choosing positive adjectives was equal to 0.67; and with negative intentions this frequency was 0.5 (Adams-Webber, 1997; Adams-Webber & Rodney, 1983). Therefore, the reflexive model also passed this test.

Conclusion

We have described and analyzed the simplest possible model of the subject with fast reflexion, which does not contain images of others. In more complicated models, the analysis begins not by writing a function describing the subject’s choice, but by constructing a reflexive structure as a basis for the function describing behavior.

It is important to keep in mind that reflexive models are not limited to the analysis of the subject’s fixed states. From the very beginning of the development of the reflexive approach, it has employed dynamic models (Lefebvre, Baranov, and Lepsky, 1969), which are now widely used in modeling various psychological phenomena (Barton, 1994; Kelso, 1995). A recent use of the dynamic model of the reflexive subject has led to the hypothesis that one of the fundamental functions of self-awareness consists of fighting against chaos, which appears in the series of sequential cognitive computations (Lefebvre, 1999, 2001).

Finally, mathematical methods have been used successfully in modeling behavior, memory, learning, perception, and thinking. Their use in constructing models of a subject capable of being aware of the self and performing deliberate actions is a natural direction for the development of psychology.

Appendix

1. The Main Equation

The function X1 = f (x1, x2, x3), which describes the subject’s readiness to choose the positive pole, is

X1 = x1 + (1 - x1)(1 - x2)x3, ................... (1)

where x1, x2, x3 Î[0,1] (Lefebvre, 1991; 1992b).

2. A Theorem on Reflexion

The functional equation K (x1,K (x2, x3)) = x1 + (1 - x1)(1 - x2)x3, where x1, x2, x3 are any numbers from [0,1] and all values of K (x2, x3) belong to [0,1] has only one solution: K (x,y) = 1 - y + xy = F (x,y) (the proof is given in Lefebvre, 1992). It follows from this theorem that the subject can be represented as

X1 = F (x1,F (x2,x3))....................... (2)

The following function corresponds to the image of the self:

X2 = F (x2,x3) = 1 - x3 + x2x3...................................... (3)

3. The Correct Model of the Self


Correctness means that X1 = x3. It follows from (1) that the following function corresponds to the subject with the correct model of the self:

4. Automatic Choice

A choice is called automatic, if the values x1 = a, x2 = b are such that f (a,b,x3) const, where x3 is any number from [0,1]. It follows from (1) that choice is automatic if at least one of the variables (x1, x2) is equal to 1.

5. Deliberate Choice

A choice is called deliberate, if the values x1 = a, x2 = b are such that function f (a,b,x3) ºx3, where x3 is any number from [0,1]. It follows from (1) that the choice is deliberate only if x1 = x2 = 0.

6. Golden Section and Other Constants

We assume that (a) the world’s pressure toward the positive and negative poles is the same, x1 = (1/2); (b) the subject’s expectation of the pressure toward the positive pole is equal to his readiness to choose it, x2 = X1. It follows from (1) that under these conditions

If the subject’s intention has not been determined in advance, the subject has a correct model of the self, X1 = x3; then (5) transforms into the equation X12 + X1 - 1 = 0, whose solution is X1 = (Ö5-1)/2 = 0.618... . If the subject’s intention has been predetermined,

X1 = (2/3) at x3 = 1, and X1 = (1/2) at x3 = 0, as follows from (5).

References

Adams-Webber, J. (1987). Comments on Lefebvreís Model from the Perspective of Personal Construct Theory. Journal of Social and Biological Structures, 10, 2, 177-189.

Adams-Webber, J. (1995). A Pragmatic Constructivist Gambit for Cognitive Scientists. PSYCOLOQUY,

6(34).

Adams-Webber, J. (1996a). Comparing Self and Others in Fast Reflexion. International Journal of Psychology, 31, 319.

Adams-Webber, J. (1996b). Repertory Grid Technique. In Corsini, R. & Auerbach, A. J. (Eds.), Concise Encyclopedia of Psychology, New York: Wiley.

Adams-Webber, J. (1997). Self-reflexion in Evaluating Others. American Journal of Psychology, 110, 527-541.

Adams-Webber, J. & Benjafield, J. (1973). The Relation between Lexical Marking and Rating Extremity in Interpersonal Judgment. Canadian Journal of Behavioral Sciences, 5, 234-241.

Adams-Webber, J. & Rodney, (1983). Rational Aspects of Temporary Changes in Construing Self and Others. Canadian Journal of Behavioral Sciences, 15, 52-59.

Baranov, P. V. & Trudoliubov, A. F. (1969a). On a Game between a Human Subject and an Automaton exercising Reflexive Control. In Pushkin, V. N. (Ed.), Problemy Evristiki, Moscow: Vysshaya Shkola.

Baranov, P. V. & Trudoliubov, A. F. (1969b). On a Possibility of Constructing a Scheme of Reflexive Control Independent of the Game-Experimental situation. In Pushkin, V. N. (Ed.), Problemy Evristiki, Moscow: Vysshaya Shkola.

Bargh, J. A. & Chartrand, T. L. (1999). The Unbearable Automaticity of Being. American Psychologist, 54, 462-479.

Barton, S. (1994). Chaos, Self-Organization, and Psychology. American Psychologist, 49, 5-14.

Batchelder, W. H. (1987). Comments on Some Critical Issues in Lefebvreís Framework for Ethical Cognition. Journal of Social and Behavioral Structures, 10, 214-226.

Benjafield J. & Adams-Webber, J. (1976). The Golden Section Hypothesis. British Journal of Psychology, 67, 11-15.

Bonnano, G. A. & Stilling, N. A. (1986). Preference, Familiarity and Recognition after Repeated Brief Exposure to Random Geometric Shapes. American Journal of Psychology, 99, 403-415.

Hughes, C. & Cutting, A. L. (1999). Nature, Nurture, and Individual Differences in Early Understanding of Mind. Psychological Science, 10, 429-432.

Kauffman, L. (1990). Self and Mathematics. In Wheeler, H. (Ed.), The Structures of Human Reflexion, New York: Peter Lang.

Kelly, G. A. (1955). The Psychology of Personal Constructs. New York: Norton.

Kelso, J. A. S. (1997). Dinamic Patterns. Cambridge, MA: A Bradford Book.

Krylov, V. Yu. (1994). On One Model of Reflexive Behavior Distinct from Lefebvre Model. Applied Ergonomics, 1, 21-24.

Kunst-Wilson, W. R. & Zajonc, R. B. (1980). Affective Discrimination of Stimuli that Cannot Be Recognized. Science, 207, 557-558.

Lefebvre, V. A. (1967). Konfliktuyushchie Struktury (Conflicting Structures). Moscow: Vysshaya Shkola. (1973). Moscow: Radio (new enlarged edition).

Lefebvre, V. A. (1969). Devices that Optimize Their Performance as a Consequence of Interference of Man. In Pushkin, V. N. (Ed.), Problemy Evristiki, Moscow: Vysshaya Shkola.

Lefebvre, V. A. (1972). A Formal Method of Investigating Reflexive Processes. General Systems, XVII, 181-188.

Lefebvre, V. A. (1977a). The Structure of Awareness. Beverly Hills, CA: Sage Publication, Inc.

Lefebvre, V. A. (1977b). A Formal Approach to the Problem of Good and Evil. General Systems, XXII, 183-185.

Lefebvre, V. A. (1980). An Algebraic Model of Ethical Cognition. Journal of Mathematical Psychology, 22, 83-120.

Lefebvre, V. A. (1982). Algebra of Conscience. Dordrecht, Holland: Reidel.

Lefebvre, V. A. (1985). The Golden Section and an Algebraic Model of Ethical Cognition. Journal of Mathematical Psychology, 29, 289-310.

Lefebvre, V. A. (1987). The Fundamental Structures of Human Reflexion. Journal of Social and Biological Structures, 10, 129-175.

Lefebvre, V. A. (1992). A Psychological Theory of Bipolarity and Reflexivity. Lewiston, N.Y.: The Edwin Mellen Press.

Lefebvre, V. A. (1995). The Anthropic Principle in Psychology and Human Choice. PSYCOLOQUY, 6 (29).

Lefebvre, V. A. (1997). The Cosmic Subject. Moscow: Russian Academy of Sciences Institute of Psychology Press.

Lefebvre, V. A. (1999). Sketch of Reflexive Game Theory. Proceedings of the Workshop on Multy-Reflexive Models of Agent Behavior. Los Alamos, NM: Army Research Laboratory.

Lefebvre, V. A. (2001). Algebra of Conscience (2nd enlarged edition). Dordrecht, Holland: Kluwer Publishers.40

Lefebvre, V. A., Baranov, P. V., & Lepskiy, V. Ye. (1969). Internal Value in Reflexive Games. Engineering Cybernetics, No.4, 27-31.

Lefebvre, V. A., Lefebvre, V. D., & Adams-Webber, J. (1986). Modeling an Experiment on Construing Self and Others. Journal of Mathematical Psychology, 30, 317-330.

Lepsky, V. E. (1969). A Study of Reflexive Processes in an Experiment on a Matrix Zero-Sum Game. In Pushkin, V. N. (Ed.): Problemy Evristiki, Moscow: Vysshaya Shkola.

Levitin, L. (1987). Niels Bohrís Atom and Vladimir Lefebvreís ´Inner Computerª. Journal of Social and Biological Structures, 10, 183-185.

Mandler, G., Nakamura, Y., & VanZandt, B. J. S. (1987). Nonspecific Effects of Exposure on Stimuli that Cannot Be Recognized. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory, and Cognition, 13, 646-648.

Miller, L. D. & Sulkoski, M. F. (1999). Reflexive Model of Human Behavior: Variations on Lefebvreís Theme. Proceedings of the Workshop on Multi-Reflexive Models of Agent Behavior. Los Alamos, NM: Army Research Laboratory.

Popper, K. (1992). Note in the Appendix to Lefebvre, V. A., A Psychological Theory of Bipolarity and Reflexivity. Lewiston, N.Y.: The Edwin Mellen Press.

Rapoport, A. (1990). Reflexion, Modeling, and Ethics. In Wheeler, H. (Ed.): The Structure of Human Reflexion. New York: Peter Lang.

Schreider, J. A. (1994). Fuzzy Sets and the Structure of Human Reflexion. Applied Ergonomics, 1, 19-20.

Schreider, J. A. (1998). Etika (Ethics). Moscow: Tekst.

Seamon, J. G., Brody, N., & Kauff, D. M. (1983). Affective Discrimination of Stimuli that are not Recognized: Effects of Shadowing, Masking, and Cerebral Laterality. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory, and Cognition, 9, 544-555.

Townsend, J. T. (1983). Vladimir A. Lefebvre. Algebra of Conscience (book review). Journal of Mathematical Psychology, 27, 461-471.

Townsend, J. T. (1990). Lefebvreís Human Reflexion and Its Scientific Acceptance in Psychology. In Wheeler, H. (Ed.), The Structures of Human Reflexion, New York: Peter Lang.

Wegner, D. M. & Wheatley, T. (1999). Apparent Mental Causation. American Psychologist, 54, 480-492.

Wheeler, H. (1987). A Constructional Biology of Hermeneutics. Journal of Social and Biological Structures, 10, 2, 103-123.

Zajonc, R. B. (1968). Attitudinal Effects of Mere Exposure. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology. Monograph supplement. 9, 2, part.2, 1-27.

Zajonc, R. B. (1987). Comment on Interpersonal Affiliation and the Golden Section. Journal of Social and Biological Structures, 212-214.

On page "Library"